THE SUPERSTITION OF SCIENCE

 

Rene Guenon

 

The civilization of the modern West has, among other pretentions, that of being eminently “scientific”; it would be as well to make it a little clearer how this term is to be understood, but that is not what is usually done, for it is one of those words to which our contemporaries seem to attach a sort of mysterious power, in-dependent of their meaning. “Science,” with a capital letter, like “Progress” and “Civilization,” like “Right,” “Justice,” and “Liberty,” is another of those entities which are better left undefined, and which run the risk of losing all their prestige as soon as they are inspected a little too closely. In this way all the so-called “conquests” which the modern world is so proud of amount to high-sounding words behind which there is nothing or else something insignificant: we have called it collective suggestion; and. the illusion which it leads to, kept up as it is and shared by so many people; cannot possibly be spontaneous. Perhaps one day we will try to throw a little light on this side of, the question. But for the moment that is not what we are directly concerned with; we simply note that the modern West believes in the ideas which we have just mentioned, if indeed they may be called ideas, however this belief may have come to it. They are not really ideas, because many of those who pro­nounce, these words with the greatest conviction have in thought nothing very clear that corresponds to them; actually there is nothing there in most cases but the expression, one might even say the personification, Of-more or less vague sentimental aspirations. These are veritable idols; the divinities of a sort of “lay religion,” which is not clearly defined, no doubt, and which cannot be, but which has none the less a very real existence: it is not religion in the proper sense of the word, but it is what pretends to take its place; and what better deserves to be called “counter-religion.” The origin of this state ,of things can be traced back to the very beginning of the modern epoch, where the ant traditional spirit showed itself at once by the proclaiming of “Tree examination,” or, in other words, the absence, in the doctrinal order, of any principle-higher than individual opinions. The inevitable result was intellectual anarchy; hence the indefinite multiplicity of religious and pseudo-religious sects, philosophic systems aiming above all at originality, and scientific theories as pretentious as they are ephemeral, in short, unbelievable chaos which is, however, dominated by a certain unity, there being beyond doubt a specifically modern out-look which is the source of it all, though this unity is altogether negative, since it is nothing more or less than an absence of principle, expressed by that indifference with regard to truth and error which ever since the XVIIIth century has been called “tolerance.” Let our meaning be quite clear; we have no intention of blaming practical tolerance as applied to individuals, out only theoretic tolerance, which claims to be applied to ideas as well and to recognise the same rights for them all, which if taken logically can only imply a rooted scepticism. Moreover we cannot help noticing that, like all propagandists, the apostles of tolerance, truth to tell, are vets often the most intolerant of men. This is what has in fact happened, and it is strangely ironical: those who wished to overthrow all dogma have created for their own use, we will not say a new dogma, but a caricature of dogma, which they have succeeded in imposing on the Western world in general; in this way there have been established, under the pretext of “freedom of thought,” the most chimerical beliefs that have ever been seen at any time, under the form of these different idols, of which we have just singled out some of the more important.

Of all the superstitions preached by those very people who profess that they never stop inveighing against “superstition,” that of “science” and “reason” is the only one which does not seem, at first sight, to be based on sentiment; but there is a kind of .rationalism which is nothing more than sentimentalism disguised, as is shown only too well by the passion with which its champions uphold it, and by the hatred which they evince for whatever goes against their inclinations or passes their comprehension. Besides, since rationalism, in any case, corresponds to a lessening of intellectuality, it is natural that its development should go hand in hand with that of sentimentalism, as we ,explained in The last chapter[1] but either one of these two tendencies may be more particularly, represented by certain individualities or by certain currents of thought, and, by reason of the more or less exclusive and system­atic terms in which they have come to be clothed, there may even be apparent con­flicts between.-them, which hide their fundamental fellowship from the eyes of superficial onlookers. Modern rationalism begins, in short, with Descartes (it had even had some forerunners in the XVIth century) and its tracks can be followed throughout all modern philosophy, no. less than in the domain which is properly speaking scientific. The present reaction of intuitionism and pragmatism against this rationalism, gives us an example of one of these conflicts, and we have seen mean-while that Bergson entirely accepts the Cartesian definition of intelligence; it is not the nature of intelligence that is questioned, but only its supremacy. In the XVIIIIth century there was also antagonism between the rationalism of the encyclopedias and the sentimentalism of Rousseau; both these, however, served equally to help on the revolutionary movement, which shows that each of them has its place in the negative unity of the anti-traditional outlook. If we cite this example in connection with the preceding one, it is not that we attribute any hidden political motive to Bergson; but we cannot help thinking of the use made of his ideas in certain syndicalist circles, especially in England, while in other circles of the same kind the “scientific” spirit is held more in honour than ever. Indeed, one of the great clevernesses of those who “control” the modern mentality seems to consist, as it were, in brewing a potion for the public, now of rationalism, now of sentimentalism, and now of both together, as occasion demands, and their trick of holding a balance between the two shows that they are much more concerned with their own political interests than with the intellectuality of their patient. It is true that this cleverness may not always be calculated, and we have no desire to question the sincerity of any scientist, historian, or philosopher; but they are often only the apparent `”controllers,” and they, may be themselves controlled of influenced without in the least realizing it Besides, the use made of their ideas does not always correspond with their own intentions, and it would be wrong to make them directly responsible, or to blame them for not having foreseen certain more or less remote consequences; but provided that these ideas conform to one or the-other of these two tendencies, they may be used in the way which we have just described; and, being given the state of intellectual anarchy in which the West is plunged, each event would seem to suggest that every possible advantage is being taken of the disorder itself and of all that contributes to the chaotic agitation for the realizing of a rigidly determined plan. We do not want to insist on this too much, but we find it difficult not to revert to it from time to time, for we cannot admit that a whole race may be purely and simply smitten with a sort of madness which has lasted for several centuries, and there must be something after all which gives a meaning to the modern civilization: we do not believe in chance, and we are sure that every existing thing must have a cause; those who think differently are at liberty to set aside such considerations.

Now, taking the two chief tendencies of the modern mentality in turn to examine them better, and leaving for the moment sentimentalism to return to it later, we may ask ourselves this question: what exactly is this “science” that the West is so infatuated with? A Hindu, summing up most concisely the opinion of all the Orientals who have come across it, has said most justly: “Western science is ignorant knowledge.”[2] This expression is in no way a contradiction in terms and this is what it means: it is, if one insists; -a knowledge-that has some reality, since it is valid and ef­fective in one relative domain’; but it is a hopelessly limited knowledge, ignorant of the essential, a knowledge which, like everything else that belongs in particular to Western civilization, lacks a principle. Science, as conceived by our contemporaries, is nothing more than the study of sensible phenomena, and this study is undertaken and followed out in such a way that it cannot, we insist, be attached to any principle of a higher order; it is true that by resolutely ignoring everything that lies beyond its scope, it makes itself fully independent in its own domain, but this boasted independence is only made possible by the very limitation of science. Not content with that, it goes even to the length of denying what it is ignorant of, because only so can it avoid admitting this ignorance: or, if it does not venture in so many words to deny the possible existence of what does not come within its range, it at least denies all possibility of knowing such things, which amounts to the same, and it has the pretention of comprising in itself everything that can be known. Starting often unconsciously from a false assumption, the “scientists” imagine, as did Auguste Comte, that man has never aimed at knowing anything other than an explanation of natural phenomena; we say unconsciously, because they are evidently incapable of understanding that it is possible to go further, and it is not for this that we blame them, but only for their pretention of refusing to allow others the possession or the use of faculties which they themselves lack; they are like blind men, who deny the existence of sight, if not of light itself, for the sole reason that they are without it. To declare that there is not only an unknown but also an “unknowable” (to use Spencer’s word), and to turn an intellectual infirmity into a barrier which no one may pass — that is something whose like was never seen or heard before; and it is equally unheard of for men to turn a declaration of ignorance into a programme of thought and a profession of faith, and quite openly to label a so-called doctrine with it under the name of “agnosticism.” And these men, be it noted, are not sceptics, and do not wish to he sceptics: if they were, there would be a certain logic in their attitude, which might make it excusable: but they are, on the contrary, the most enthusiastic believers in “science,” the most fervent admirers of “reason.” It might well be considered rather strange to put reason above everything, to profess a veritable worship for it, and to proclaim at the same time that it is essentially limited; that is, in fact, somewhat contradictory, and though we note it, we do not undertake to explain’ it; this attitude points to a mentality which is not in the least our own, and it is not for us to justify the contradictions which seem inherent in “relativism” in .all its forms. We, too, say that reason is limited and relative: but, far from making it the whole of intelligence, we look on it only as one of its inferior parts, and we see in intelligence other, possibilities which go far beyond those of reason.. It, seems then. that modern Europeans, or at least some of them, are very willing to acknowledge their. ignorance, and the rationalists of to-day do so per­haps more readily than their predecessors, but it is only on condition that no one has the right to know what they themselves do not; the pretention of limiting what is,, or just of limiting, knowledge fundamentally, shows in either case the spirit of negation which is so characteristic of the modern world. This spirit of negation is nothing other than the systematic spirit, for a system is essentially a closed concep­tion; and it has come to be identified with the spirit of philosophy itself, especially since Kant, who, wishing to shut up all knowledge within the bounds of relativity, ventured to declare in so many words that “philosophy is not a means of extending knowledge but a discipline for limiting it,”[3] which amounts to saying that the chief function of philosophers is to impose on all the narrow limits of their own under-standing. That is why modern philosophy ends by almost entirely substituting “criticism” or the “theory of knowledge” for knowledge itself; that is also why many of its representatives no longer claim for it a higher title than “scientific philosophy,” or, in other words, mere co-ordination of the most general results of science, whose domain is the only one it recognizes as being accessible to intelligence. In these circumstances philosophy and science are not to be distinguished, and in actual fact, since the birth of rationalism; they can only have had one and the same object, they have only represented a single order of knowledge, they have been animated by the self-same spirit: it is this that we call, not the scientific spirit, but the “scientist” spirit.

We must insist a little on this last distinction: what we wish to indicate by it is that we see no essential harm in the development of certain sciences, even if we find that far too much importance is given them; it is only a very relative knowledge, but it is none the less a knowledge, and it is right that everyone should turn his in­tellectual activity on to what suits his natural talents and the means at his disposal. What we object to is the exclusiveness, we might say the sectarianism, of those who have been so intoxicated by the lengths to which these sciences have been stretched that they refuse to admit the existence of anything apart from them, and maintain that, to be valid, every speculation must be submitted to the methods which are peculiar to these same sciences, as if these methods, created for the study of certain fixed objects, were universally applicable. It is true that their conception of universality is something very limited which certainly does not pass beyond the domain of contingency. But these “scientists” would be most astonished if told that, without even leaving this domain, there is a host of things which cannot be got at by their methods and which notwithstanding may be made the object of sciences quite dif­ferent from the ones they know, but no less real and often more interesting in many respects. It seems that men to-day have taken arbitrarily, in the domain of scientific knowledge, a certain number of parts which they have frenziedly set about studying to the exclusion of all the rest and on the assumption that this rest is inexistent; and it-is quite natural, and not in the least surprising or admirable, that they should have given these particular sciences which they have so cultivated a much larger development than could men who did not attach anything like the same importance to them, who often scarcely even bothered about them, and who were in any case concerned with many other things which seemed to them more important. We are thinking above all of the considerable development of the experimental sciences, a domain where the modern West clearly excels, and where no one dreams of contest­ing its superiority, which moreover, as the Orientals see it, is a scarcely enviable one, for the very reason that it could only be bought at the expense of forgetting all that they hold truly worthy of interest. However, we have no hesitation in stating that there are sciences, even experimental ones, of which the modern West has not the least idea. Such sciences exist in the East, among those which we call “traditional sciences”. Even in the West, there were also during the Middle Ages such sciences, altogether equivalent in some respects; and these sciences, some of which even give rise to undeniably efficient practical applications, are carried out by means of in­vestigation altogether unknown to the “authorities” of modern Europe. This is cer­tainly not the place for us to enlarge on the subject; but we should at least explain why we say that certain branches of scientific knowledge have a traditional basis, and what we mean by this; and y doing so we shall in fact be showing, still more clearly than we have done so far, what Western science lacks.

We have said that one of the special features of this Western science is the pretention of being entirely independent and autonomous; and this can only be upheld by systematically ignoring all knowledge of a higher order than scientific knowledge, or better still by formally denying it. What is above science, in the necessary hierarchy of knowledge, is metaphysic,[4] which is pure and transcendent intellectual knowledge, while science, by its very definition, is only rational know-ledge. Metaphysic is essentially super-rational; it must be that, or else not be at all. Now rationalism consists, not in simply stating that reason has some value, which only the sceptics contest, but in maintaining that there is nothing above it, or, in other words, that there is no knowledge possible beyond scientific knowledge; thus rationalism necessarily implies the negation of metaphysic. Almost all modern philosophers are rationalists, more or less narrowly and more or less outspokenly; among those who are not, there is only sentimentalism and voluntarism, which is no less anti-metaphysical, because having reached this state, if they admit anything other than reason, it is below reason that they look for it, instead of looking above; true intellectualism is at least as remote from rationalism as modern intuitionism can be, but it is so in exactly the inverse direction. In these circumstances, if a modern philosopher claims to be concerned with metaphysic, one may be sure that what he so names has absolutely nothing in common with true metaphysic, and such is indeed the case; we can only allow these pre-occupations the title of “pseudo-meta­physic,” and if none the less some valid considerations are occasionally to be found amongst them, they belong really to the scientific order pure and simple. The general features, then, of characteristically modern thought are these: complete ab­sence of metaphysical knowledge, negaticn of all knowledge that is not scientific, and arbitrary limitation of scientific knowledge itself to certain particular domains, excluding the rest; such is the depth of intellectual degradation to which the West has sunk since it left those paths that the rest of mankind follows as a matter of course.[5]

Metaphysic is the knowledge of the universal principles on which all things necessarily depend, directly or indirectly; in the absence of metaphysic, any other knowledge, of whatever order it may be, is literally lacking in principle, and if by that it gains a little in independence (not as a right, but as a matter of fact), it loses much more in import and depth. That is why Western science is, as it were, all on the surface. While scattering its energies among countless fragments of knowledge, and losing its way among the innumerable details of fact, it learns nothing about the true nature of things, which it declares to be inaccessible in order to justify its powerlessness in this respect; thus its interest is much more practical than speculative. If there are sometimes attempts to unify this eminently analytical learning, they are purely artificial and are never based on anything but more or less wild sup-positions; and they all collapse one after the other, until it seems that no scientific theory of any general bearing can last more than half a century at the most. Besides, the Western idea which would make synthesis a sort of result and conclusion of analysis is radically false; the truth is that a synthesis worthy of the name can never be reached by analysis, because one belongs to one order of things and the other to an-other. By its very nature, analysis may be carried out indefinitely, if its field of ac­tion is expansive enough, without one’s having got any nearer to a general view over the whole field; it is still less surprising that it should be utterly ineffectual in establishing a connection with principles of a higher order. The analytical character of modern science is shown by the ceaseless growth in the number of “specialities” the dangers of which Auguste Comte himself could not help pointing out. This “specialization,” so gloried in by certain sociologists under the name of “division of labour,” is the best and surest way of acquiring this “intellectual short-sightedness,” which seems to be among the qualifications demanded of the perfect “scientist,” and with-out which, moreover, “scientism” itself would have scarcely any hold. And the “specialists” once brought outside their own domain, generally show themselves to be unbelievably ingenuous; nothing is easier than to impose on them, and this is what contributes in good part to the success of the most idiotic theories, provided that care is taken to call them “scientific.” The most idle suppositions, like that of evolution for example, take the rank of “laws” and are held for proven; and though this success is only temporary, their riddance means that their place has been taken by something else which is always accepted with equal readiness. False syntheses which are bent on extracting the superior from the inferior (a strange transposition of the conception-of democracy), can never be anything more than hypothetical: true synthesis, on the contrary, starting from the principles, partakes of their cer­tainty; but it is of course true principles which must be the starting point, and not mere philosophic assumptions in the manner of Descartes. In short it may be said that science, in disavowing the principles and in refusing to re-attach itself to them, robs itself both of the highest guarantee and of the surest direction that it could have; there is no longer anything valid in it except knowledge of details, and as soon as it seeks to rise one degree higher, it becomes dubious and vacillating. Another consequence of what we have just said about the relations between analysis and syn­thesis is that the development of science, as the moderns understand it, does not really extend its domain; the amount of fragmentary knowledge may increase indefi­nitely within this domain, not through deeper penetration, but through division and subdivision carried out always more and more minutely; it is indeed the science of matter and multitude. Besides, even if there should be a real extension, as may happen exceptionally, it would always be within the same order, and it would not enable this science to rise any higher; in its present state it is separated from its prin­ciples by an abyss which, far from being bridgeable, cannot even be made the least little fraction less.

When we say that the sciences, even experimental sciences, have in the East a traditional basis, we mean that, unlike Western ones, they are always attached to certain principles; these are never lost sight of, and what is contingent seems only worth studying in that it is a consequence and outward manifestation of something which belongs to a higher order. True, there remains none the less a profound distinction between metaphysical knowledge and scientific knowledge; but there is not an absolute discontinuity between them, such as is to be noticed in the present state of scientific knowledge in the West. We can take an example even within the Western world, if we consider all the distance which separates the standpoint of ancient and mediaeval cosmology from that of physics as understood by the moderns; never, until the present epoch, had the study of the sensible world been regarded as self-sufficient; never would the science of this changing and ephemeral multiplicity have been judged truly worthy of the name of knowledge, unless the means had been found of connecting it, in some degree or other, with something stable and perma­nent. According to the ancient conception, which the Orientals have always kept to, a science was less esteemed for itself than for the degree in which it expressed after its own fashion and represented within a certain order of things a reflection of the higher immutable truth which everything of any reality necessarily partakes of; and, as the features of this truth were incarnated, as it were, in the idea of tradition, all science appeared as an extension of the traditional doctrine itself, as one of its applications, secondary and contingent no doubt, accessory and not essential, constituting an inferior knowledge, but still a veritable knowledge none the less, since it kept a link with that supreme knowledge which belongs to the order of pure intellect. It is clear that this conception is absolutely irreconcilable with the gross practical naturalism which shuts up our contemporaries within the sole domain of contingency, one may even say, to be more exact, within a narrow portion of this domain;’’[6] and as the Orientals, we repeat, have not varied in this conception and cannot do so without denying the principles on which all their civilization is based, the two mentalities appear to be decidedly incompatible; but since it is the West that has changed, and since it never ceases to change, perhaps a moment will come when its mentality will be modified for the better and become open to a wider understanding, and then this incompatibility will vanish of itself.

We think we have shown clearly enough how far the Orientals’ appraisal of Western science is justified; and, under these conditions, there is only one thing which can explain the unbounded admiration and superstitious respect that is lavished on this science: this is its perfect harmony with the needs of a purely material civilization. There is, in fact, no question here of disinterested speculation; those minds which are altogether engrossed by outward things are struck by the applica­tions that science gives rise to, and by its above all practical and utilitarian charac­ter; and it is especially thanks to the mechanical inventions that the “scientist” spirit has had its development. These are the inventions which have aroused, since the beginning of the XIXth century, a positively delirious enthusiasm, because their ob­jective seems to be the increase of bodily comfort, which is clearly the chief aspira­tion of the modern world. Moreover, there were thus created unawares in addition more new needs than could be satisfied, so that even from this very relative point of view, progress is most illusory; and, once launched upon this course, it seems no longer possible to stop, as there is always some new want to be supplied. But how-ever that may be, it is these applications, confused with science itself, which more than anything else have made for its credit and prestige; this confusion, which could only arise among people ignorant of what pure speculation is, even in the scientific order, has become so usual that to-day, on opening no matter what publication, one finds constantly under the name of “science” what ought properly to be called “in­dustry”; the typical “authority” is, in most minds, the engineer, the inventor or constructor of machines. As for scientific theories, they must be considered much more as profiteers from this state of mind than as the causes of it; if those very people who are least capable of understanding them accept them with confidence and receive them as veritable dogma (and the less they understand the more easily they are deluded) it is because they look on them, wrongly or rightly, as closely bound up with these practical inventions which they deem so marvellous. Actually this closeness is much more apparent than real; the more or less inconsistent “scientist” hypotheses play no part in these discoveries and these applications, on the interest of which opinions may differ, but which have in any case the merit of being something effective; and, inversely, all that can be realized in the practical order will never prove the truth of any hypothesis. Besides, in a more general way, there could not, properly speaking, be a verification of a hypothesis by experiment, for it is always possible to find several theories which explain equally well the same facts. Certain hypotheses may be eliminated when they are seen to be in contradiction with the facts, but those which are left remain always mere hypotheses and nothing more; this is not the way that certainties could ever be arrived at. However, for men who accept nothing but hard facts, and who have no other criterion of truth than “experience,’:-by, which they simply mean the noticing of sensible phenomena, there can be no question of going further or of proceeding otherwise, and, for such as these, there are only two attitudes possible: either to take one’s tone from the realization that scientific theories are hypothetical, and to renounce all certainty higher than mere sensible evidence; or, refusing to admit that they are hypothetical, to believe blindly everything that is taught in the name of “science.” The former attitude, assuredly more intelligent than the latter (always remembering the limita­tions of “scientific” intelligence), is that of certain “authorities” who, being less ingenuous than the others, refuse to be the dupes of their own or their fellows’ hypotheses. Thus, except for what is immediately practical, they arrive at a state of more or less complete scepticism or at least at a sort of probabilism: it is “agnostic-ism” no longer applied simply to what goes beyond the domain of science, but extended even to the scientific order itself. They only emerge from this negative attitude by a more or less conscious pragmatism, having regard, like Henri Poincare, no longer to the truth of a hypothesis but instead to its convenience; is that not an admission of incurable ignorance? Meanwhile, the second attitude, which may be called dogmatic, is mataintained with more or less sincerity by other “authorities,” but especially by those who believe themselves bound for the needs of education to be affirmative: to appear always sure of oneself and of what one says, to cover up the difficulties and the uncertainties, never to give anything out under a dubitative form is indeed the easiest way to make sure of being taken seriously and to acquire authority in one’s dealings with a public that is generally incompetent and incapable of discernment, whether t is pupils that are being addressed, or whether the task in hand is one of popularization. This same attitude is naturally taken up, and this time with incontestable sincerity, by those who receive such an education; also it is commonly the attitude of what is called “the man in the street,” and. the “scientist” outlook can be seen in all its fullness, with this characteristic blind belief, among men who have only been semi-educated, in circles reigned over by that mentality which is often qualified as “primary,” although this mentality is not confined to those who have had a “primary” education.

We spoke just now of “popularization”; that is another thing altogether pecu­liar to modern civilization and in it may be seen one of the chief factors of this state of mind which we are trying to describe. It is one of the forms taken by this strange need for propaganda which animates the Western mind, and which can only be ex­plained by the predominant influence of sentiment; no intellectual consideration justifies proselytism, in which the Orientals see nothing but a proof of ignorance and incomprehension; there is a complete difference between simply expounding the truth as one has understood it, with the one care not to disfigure it, and wishing at any price to make others share one’s own conviction. Propaganda and popularization are not even possible except to the detriment of the truth: the pretention of putting it “within everyone’s grasp,” of making it accessible to all without distinction, necessarily involves diminishing and deforming it, for it is impossible to admit that all men are equally capable of understanding anything; it is not a question of the greater or smaller extent of education, it is a question of “intellectual horizon,” and that is something which cannot be modified, which is inherent in the very nature of each human individual. The chimerical prejudice of “equality” goes against all the best established facts, in the intellectual order as well as in the physi­cal order; it is the negation of all natural hierarchy, and it is the debasement of all knowledge to the revel of the limited understanding of the mass., People will no longer admit anything which passes common comprehension, and, in fact, the scientific and philosophic conceptions of our epoch are, all told, most lamentably medio­cre: modern “authorities” have succeeded only too well in wiping out all that might have been incompatible with the concern for popularization. Whatever anyone may say, the constitution of any elect cannot be reconciled with the democratic ideal, which demands that one and the same education shall be given to individuals who are most unequally gifted, and who differ widely both in talents and temperament; inevitably the results still continue to vary, in spite of this education, but that is contrary to the intentions of those who instituted it. In any case such a system of teaching is assuredly the most imperfect of all, and the indiscriminate diffusion of scraps of knowledge is always more harmful than beneficial, for it can only bring about a general state of disorder and anarchy. It is such a diffusion that is guarded against by the methods of traditional teaching, as it exists throughout the East, where there will always be far more conviction of the very real inconveniences of “compulsory education” than of its imagined benefits. As if it were not already enough that the knowledge which is available to Westerners is entirely untranscendant, it is still further diminished in the works of popularization, which only treat of its most inferior aspects, and that too with distortions in order to make them simpl­er; and these works insist complacently on the most fantastic hypotheses, having the effrontery to give them out as proven truths, and accompanying them with those inept declamations which so please the mob. A half-knowledge acquired by such reading, or by an education whose elements are all drawn from hand-books of a like value, is far more injurious than pure and simple ignorance; better for a man to know nothing at all than to have his mind encumbered with false ideas, often ineradicable, especially when they have been inculcated from his earliest years. The ignorant man retains at least the possibility of learning if he is given the opportunity: he may possess a certain natural “common sense” which, together with the consciousness that he ordinarily has of his own incompetence, is enough to save him from much folly. On the contrary, the man who has been half taught has nearly always a deformed mentality, and what he thinks he knows makes him so self-satisfied that he imagines himself capable of talking about everything, no matter what; he does so at random, and the greater his incompetence the greater his glibness: so simple do all things appear to one who knows nothing!

Besides, even setting aside the evils of popularization itself and considering Western science as a whole and under its most authentic aspects, there remains, in the claim that the representatives of this science advertise of being able to teach it to all without any reserve, a sign of clear mediocrity. In the eyes of the Orientals there can be no great value and no true depth of contents in something whose study calls for no particular qualification; and, in fact, Western science is altogether out-ward and superficial; to characterize it, instead of saying “ignorant knowledge” we would be willing to say, with very much the same meaning, “profane knowledge.” There is no real distinction, from this point of view any more than from the others, to be made between philosophy and science. People have sought to define philosophy as “human wisdom”; indeed it is, but with the strong reserve that it is nothing more than that, a wisdom purely human, in the most limited acceptation of this word, derived from no element of a higher order than reason; to avoid all uncertainty we would call it also “profane wisdom,” but that amounts to saying that it is not really a wisdom at all, but only the illusory appearance of one. We will not insist here on the consequences of this “profane” character of all modern Western knowledge; but to show further how superficial and sham this knowledge is, we will call to notice that the methods of teaching in use have the effect of replacing intelligence almost entirely by memory. What is demanded of the pupils, from the time they first go to a primary school to the time they leave the university, is that they should hoard up as much as possible of what is taught them, not that they should assimilate it; those things are especially worked at whose study requires no comprehension; facts are substituted for ideas, and scholarship is commonly mistaken for real knowledge. To promote or to discredit this or that branch of knowledge, this or that method, no more is needed than to declare that it is or is not “scientific”; what are accounted officially as “scientific methods” are the most unintelligent methods of learning, methods which exclude everything which is not research after facts for facts’ sake down to their most insignificant details; and it is worth noting that the worst abusers of this denomination are the “men of letters.” The prestige of this label “scientific,” even when it is really nothing more than a label, is indeed the triumph of triumphs for the “scientist” mind; and as for the respect which is extorted from the masses (including the so called “intellectuals”) by the use of a simple word, are we not right in calling it “the superstition of science”?

Of course “scientist” propaganda is not carried on only within the West, under the double form of “compulsory education” and popularization; it is rife also outside, like all the other varieties of Western proselytism. Everywhere that the Europeans have installed themselves, they have wanted to spread these so-called “benefits of education,” always following the same methods, without the least at-tempt to adapt them and without it entering their heads that there may be already some other kind of education there. Everything that does not come from them is to be considered as null and void, and “equality” does not allow different peoples and different races to have their own mentality; moreover the chief “advantage” that the imposers of this education expect from it is probably, always and everywhere, the blotting out of the traditional outlook. The “equality” so dear to Westerners amounts moreover, as soon as they leave their home, to mere uniformity; the rest of what it implies does not come into the category of “exportable goods” and only concerns the relations between one Westerner and another, for they believe them-selves incomparably superior to all other men, among whom they scarcely make any distinctions: the most barbarous negroes and the most cultured Orientals are treated in almost the same way, because they are equally outside the one “civilization” which has the right to exist. Also the Europeans usually confine themselves to teaching the most rudimentary fragments of all their knowledge; it is not hard to imagine how these fragments must be appreciated by the Orientals, to whom even what is highest in this knowledge would seem chiefly remarkable for its narrowness, and stamped with a rather gross ingenuousness. As the peoples who have a civilization of their own prove themselves on the whole ret rectory to this so much boasted education, while the peoples without culture submit to it much more docilely, Westerners are perhaps not far from judging the latter superior to the former; they are prepared to show at least a relative esteem for those whom they look on as susceptible of “ris­ing” to their level, even though this elevation be considered only possible after some centuries of the regime of compulsory elementary education. Unfortunately, what the people of the West call “rising” would be called by some, as far as they are con­cerned, “sinking”; that is what all true Orientals think, even if they do not say so, and if they prefer, as most often happens, to hedge themselves round with the most disdainful silence, leaving, so little does it matter to them, Western vanity free to interpret their attitude as it pleases.

The Europeans have so high an opinion of their science that they believe its prestige to be irresistible, and they imagine that the other peoples must fall down in admiration before their most insignificant discoveries; this state of mind, which leads them sometimes into strange misunderstandings, is not altogether new, and we have found a rather amusing example of it in Leibnitz. This philosopher, as is known, had planned to establish what he called a “universal characteristic,” that is a sort of generalized algebra, made applicable to the notions of every order, instead of being limited to quantitative notions alone; moreover this idea had been inspired in him by certain authors of the Middle Ages, especially Raymond Lulle and Trithemius. in the course of the studies which he made towards realizing this project, Leibnitz came to be engrossed with the meaning of the ideographic characters which consti­tute Chinese writing, and more particularly with the symbolical figures which form the basis of the Yi-king; it will be seen how he understood these last: “Leibnitz,” says M. Couturat, “believed he had found by his binary numeration (a numeration which only employs the signs O and I and in which he saw the image of creation exnihilo) the interpretation of the characters of Fo-hi, mysterious and remotely ancient Chinese symbols, whose meaning was unknown to the European missionaries and to the Chinese themselves. . . . He proposed to use this interpretation for the propaganda of the Faith in China, seeing that it was fit to give the Chinese a high idea of European science, and to show the accordance of this science with the venerable and sacred traditions of Chinese wisdom. He added this interpretation to the exposition of his binary arithmetic which he sent to the Paris Academy of Sciences.’’’ Here, in fact, is the text of the thesis in question: “What is surprising in this calculus (of binary Arithmetic) is that this Arithmetic by O and I happens to contain the mystery of the lines of an ancient King and Philosopher named Fohy, who is believed to have lived more than four thousand years ago and whom, the Chinese re­gard as the Founder of their Empire and of their sciences. There are several linear figures which are attributed to him, and they are all the outcome of this Arithme­tic; but it is enough to give here the Figure of eight Cove,[7] as it is called, which passes for fundamental, and to add the explanation which is clear, so long as it be noticed first of all that a whole line signifies unity or I, and secondly, that a borken line signifies zero or 0. It is perhaps more than a thousand years since the Chinese lost the meaning of the Cova or Lineations of Fohy, and they have made commentaries about it, in which they have sought to give I know not what remote interpretations, so that they have now had to receive the true one from the Europeans. This is how: it is scarcely more than two years since I sent to the Rev. Father Bouvet, a celebrated French Jesuit living at Pekin, my way of counting by 0 and I, and it needed no more to make him realize that it is the key to the figures of Fohy. So, writing to me on November 17th, 1701, he sent me this Philosopher-Prince’s great figure, which goes up to 64,[8] and leaves no longer any room for doubting the truth of our interpretation, so that one may say that this Father has deciphered the enigma of Fohy with the aid of what I had communicated to him. And as these figures are perhaps the most ancient monument of science in the world, this restitution of their meaning, after so great an interval of time, will seem all the more curious… And this accordance gives me a high opinion of the depth of Fohy’s meditations. For what we now find easy was not all so in those remote times… And as it is believed in China that Fohy is as well the author of the Chinese characters, although they have been much changed by the lapse of time, his essay in Arithmetic leads one to judge that there might well be something else of import there in relation to numbers and to ideas, if the foundation of Chinese writing could be laid bare, the more so as it is believed in China that he had regard to numbers in establishing it The Rev. Father Bouvet is much inclined to press this point, and very capable of succeeding in many respects. However, I know not if there has ever been in Chinese writing an advantage approaching that which should necessarily be in a Characteristic that I am planning. This is that all reasoning which may be deduced from notions, might be deduced from their Characters by a manner of calculation, which would be one of the chief means of aiding the human mind.”[9] We were anxious to reproduce at length this curious document, by means of which one may measure the limits in understanding of the man whom we none the less regard as the most “intelligent” of all the modern philosophers. Leibnitz was convinced in advance that his “characteristic,” which moreover he never succeeded in constituting (and the logisticians of to-day are scarcely more advanced), could not fail to be very superior to the Chinese ideography; and the best of all is that he thinks to do Fo-hi great honour in attributing to him an essay in arithmetic” and the first idea of his own little play on numbers. We seem to see here the smile of the Chinese, if they had been presented with this rather puerile interpretation, which would have been very far from giving them “a high idea of European science,” but which would have been fit to make them realize very, exactly its actual range. The truth is that the Chinese have. never “lost the meaning,” or rather the meanings, of the symbols in question; only they do not feel themselves in the least obliged to explain them to the first-comer, especially if they judge that it would be a waste of breath; and Leibnitz, in speaking of “I know not what remote interpretations” admits in so many words that he understands nothing about it. It is just these interpretations, carefully preserved by the tradition (which the commentaries never cease to follow faithfully), that constitute “the true explanation,” and moreover they are not in the least “mystical”; but what better proof of incomprehension could be given than the taking of metaphysical symbols for “purely numerical characters”? They are, in fact, essentially metaphysical symbols, these “trigrams” and “hexagrams,” a synthetic representation of theories which are susceptible of unlimited developments, susceptible’ also of multiple adaptations, if, instead of keeping to the domain of the principles, one wishes to apply them to one or another determined order of things. Leibnitz would have been most surprised if he had been told that his arithmetical interpretation was also included among these meanings which he rejected without knowing, bit only on an altogether accessory and subordinate level; for this interpretation is not false in itself, and it is perfectly compatible with all the others, but it is quite incomplete and insufficient, even insignificant when considered b’ Itself, and may only be held interesting in virtue of the analogical correspondence which binds up the lower, meanings with the higher one, in accordance with what we have said about the nature of the “traditional sciences.” The higher meaning is the pure metaphysical meaning; as for the rest, they are only different applications, more or less important, but always contingent; it is in this way that there may be an arithmetical application just as there are an indefinite number of others, just as there is for example a logical application, which might have better served the turn of Leibnitz’s project if he had been aware of it, just as there is a social application, which is the basis of Confucianism, just as there is an astrono­mical application, the only one that the Japanese have ever been able to grasp,[10] just as there is even a divinatory application, which moreover the Chinese look on as one of the lowest of all, and the practice of which they leave to the wandering jugglers. If Leibnitz had been in direct contact with the Chinese, they might have explained to him (but would he have understood?) that even the numbers which he used might symbolize ideas of an order much more profound than the order of mathematics, and that it is by reason of such a symbolism that numbers played a part in the formation of the ideograms, no less than in the expression of the Pythagorean doctrines (which shows that these things were not unknown to the ancients of the West). The Chinese might even have accepted the notation by 0 and I, and have taken these “purely numerical characters” to represent symbolically the metaphysical ideas of yin and of yang (which have moreover nothing to do with the conception of the creation ex nihilo), there being none the less many reasons for them to prefer, as more adequate, the representation furnished by Fo-hi’s “lineations,” of which the essential and direct object is in the domain of metaphysic. We have treated this example at length because it shows up clearly the difference that exists between philosophical systematization and traditional synthesis, between Western science and Eastern wisdom; it is not hard to see, judging from this example which

also serves us as a symbol, on which side lie the incomprehension and the narrowness of outlook.[11] Leibnitz, in his pretention to understand the Chinese symbols better than the Chinese themselves do, is a veritable forerunner of the orientalists, who, the Germans above all, have the same pretention with regard to all the conceptions and all the doctrines of the East, and who refuse to take into the smallest consideration the opinion of the authorized representatives of these doctrines: we have mentioned elsewhere the case of Deussen thinking to explain Shankaracharya to the Hindus, and interpreting him through the ideas of Schopenhauer; these are indeed manifesta­tions of one and the same mentality.

There is still a last remark that we should make with regard to this: it is that Westerners, who advertise so insolently on every occasion belief in their own superiority and in that of their science, are really very much beside the mark when they call Eastern wisdom “arrogant,” as some of them do at times, on the grounds that it does not submit to the limitations that they are used to, and because they cannot allow what goes beyond these limitations; this is one of the habitual of faults of mediocrity, and it is mediocrity which forms the basis-of the democratic spirit. Arrogance, in reality, is something very Western; so also, moreover, is humility, and however much of a paradox that may seem, these two opposites go rather closely together: it is an example of the duality which dominates the whole order of sentiment and which is proved most obviously by the innate character of moral conceptions, for the notions of good and evil could not exist but by their very opposition. In actual fact, arrogance and humility are equally strange to Eastern wisdom (we might as well say to wisdom without epithet) and leave it equally unaffected, because in essence it is purely intellectual, and entirely detached from all sentimentality; it knows that the human being is at the same time much less and much more than it is believed to be by the people of the West, by those at least of to-day, and it knows also that it is just what it should be to occupy the place assigned to it in the order of the universe. Man, that is, human individuality, has by no means a situation that is privileged or exceptional, either one way or the other; he is neither at the top nor at the bottom of the scale of beings: he represents simply, in the hierarchy of existence, a state like the others, among the indefinity of others, many of which are above him, and many of which also are below him. It is not hard to show, even in this respect, that humility goes very steadily together with a certain kind of arro­gance: it is just, in seeking to abase man, as they often do in the West, that they find the means of attributing to him at the same time an importance which is really quite undue,, at least in so far as his individuality is concerned; perhaps it is an example of that kind of unconscious hypocrisy, which is, in one degree or another, inseparable from all “moralism,” and in which the Orientals see fairly generally one of the specific marks of the Westerner. Besides, this counterbalancing humility by no means always ._exists; there is also, among a good number of other Westerners, a veritable deification of human reason, worshipping itself either directly or through the science which is its work; it is the most extreme form of rationalism and of “scientism,” but it is their most natural outcome and altogether the most logical one. Indeed, anyone who knows nothing beyond this science and this reason may well have the illusion of their absolute supremacy; anyone who knows nothing superior to humanity, and more particularly to this type of humanity which is represented by the modern West, may be tempted to deify it, especially if senti­mentalism intrudes (and we have shown that it is far from being incompatible with rationalism). All this is only the inevitable consequence of ignorance of the principles, an ignorance which we have denounced as the capital vice of Western science; and, despite Littre’s protestations, we do not think that Auguste Comte caused the slightest deviation in positivism by wishing to set up a “religion of Humanity”; this particular “mysticism” was nothing more than an attempt at fusion of the two characteristic tendencies of the modern civilization. Worse still, there exists even a materialist pseudo-mysticism: we have known people who went to the length of declaring that even if they should have no rational motive for being materialists, they would none the less continue to be so, solely because it is “finer” to “do good” without any hope of possible recompense. These people, whose minds are so powerfully influenced by “Moralism” (and their morality, in spite of calling itself “scientific,” is none the less purely and radically sentimental), are naturally among those who profess the `”religion of science”. As this, in all truth, can only be a “pseudo-religion,” we deem it far juster to call it “superstition of science”; a belief which is only based on ignorance (even if it is that of authority”) and on vain prejudice does not deserve to be looked at in any other way than as a common superstition.

 


NOTES AND REFERENCES

[1] See Rene Guenon, “Civilization and Progress”, Iqbal Review, Vol. XXVI, No. 1, LHR, 1985. (Editor).

[2] “The Miscarriage of Life in the West,” by P. Ramanathan, Solicitor-General of Ceylon: Hibbert Journal, VII, I; quoted by Benjamin Kidd, The Science of Power, p. 95.

[3] Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, ed. Hartenstein, p. 256.

[4] With the author’s approval we have preferred to use this rarer word in transla­ting /a metaphysique, because, although the word metaphysics means “that which is beyond the domain of physics” and is not usually considered as a plural, the ending none the less suggests a collectivity, such as mathematics, physics or economics, which may be said to have sub-divisions or branches, whereas metaphysic is one undivided and indivisible whole. However, the word pseudo-metaphysics may well be used as a plural, referring to the fantastic and mutually-conflicting theories of many modern philosophers, most of whom, despite their claims, have not even a suspicion of what true metaphysic is.

[5] These comments were written in the first quarter of the 20th century when the cultures of the East were not as decadent as they grew in the later part of the century. Statements that made towards the end of his life indicate that he had re-evaluated the matter and had come to the realization that the Oriental civilizations had also succumbed to the onslaught of the Western secularist humanism, scientism and anti-intellectual tendencies. (Editor).

[6] We say practical naturalism, because this limitation is accepted by people who do not profess naturalism in its more particularly philosophical sense. In just the same way there is a positivist mentality which does not in the least pre-suppose adherence to positivism as a system.

[7] Leibnitz’s La Logique, pp. 474-475.

The exact date is 3468 B.C., according to a chronology based on the, precise description of the state of the heavens at that epoch; it should be added that actually the name Fo-hi serves to designate a whole period of Chinese history.

[8] Koua is the Chinese name for “trigrams,” that is figures obtained by assembl­ing in threes, with every possible combination, whole and broken straight lines. Actually the number of figures so obtainable is eight.

This reference is to the sixty-four “hexagrams” of Wen-Wang, that is figures of six lines formed by combining the eight “trigrams” two by two. Incidentally, Leibnitz’s interpretation is quite incapable of explaining, amongst other things, why these “hexagrams,” as well as the “trigrams” that they are derived from are always tabulated in circular form.

[9] Explanation of binary Arithmetic, which makes use of the characters 0 and I only, with remarks on its utility, and on its giving the sense of the ancient Chinese figures of Fohy, Memoires d’l’ Academic’ des Sciences, 1703: Mathe­matical works of Leibnitz, Gerhardt, Vol. VII, pp. 226-227; see also De Dyadicis: ibid., Vol. VII, pp. 223-234. This text ends as follows: “Ita mirum accidit, ut res ante ter et ampiius (millia?) annos nota in extremo ?stric continentis Oriente, nunc in extremo ejus occidente, sed inelioribus ut spero auspiciis resuscitaretur. Nam non apparet, ante usum hujus characterismi ad augendam numerorum scientiam innotuisse. Sinenses vero ipsi ne Arithmeti­cam quidem rationem intelligentes nescio quos mysticos significatus in characteribus mere numeralibus sibi fingebant.”.

[10] The French translation of the Yi-king by Philastre (Annales du Musbe Guimet, Vol. VIII and Vol. XXIII), which is moreover an extremely remarkable work, has the fault of considering rather too exclusively the astronomical meaning.

[11] We will recall here what we said of the plurality of meanings of all traditional texts, and especially of the Chinese ideograms: introduction generate a /’etude des doctrines hindoues, pp. 149-150. We will add also this quotation borrow­ed from Philastre: “In Chinese, a word (or a character) has scarcely ever an absolutely defined and limited meaning; the meaning results very generally from the position in the sentence, but above all from its use in some older book or other, and from its admitted interpretation in this case . . . A word has no value except by its traditional acceptations.” (Yi-king, Part I, page 8.).